Socialising
Analysis Through Postmodern Knowledge
(MPhil Submission, Lent Term 2012)
3500 Words
The
20th
Century saw the study of music predominantly focused on the study of
Western Art Music through analyses which took as their starting point
the 'music itself'– interpreting the structures of a work, together
with their resolution into relatively simpler elements, to show how
harmony and motives work together to form a unified whole. From the
late 1950's onwards, the quasi-scientific field of music theory and
analysis underwent rapid expansion and professionalisation in North
America, 'music theorist' becoming an esteemed professional identity
(Everett Maus 2004: 14). Although there are certainly agreed upon
methodological 'tools' (i.e. the parameters of the music itself),
there are many accepted, differing methodologies.1
Joseph
Kerman's seminal publications How We Got Into Analysis and How To
Get Out (1980) and Musicology (1985) began a substantial
weakening of faith in the methods of analysis, and a shift in focus
towards the 'cultural' values to which it has, by custom,
dichotomously opposed itself. In this essay, I will take the look at
the contributions of two authors who helped shift musicology out of
the analytic paradigm by borrowing ideas from literary theory,
whether to present a method of discussing social context –
Lawrence Kramer's Classical Music and Postmodern Knowledge, or
to present a different model of how we may look at the 'music itself'
– Rose Rosengard Subotnik's Deconstructive Variations. I
will use these texts to illustrate issues raised by the paradigm
shift, and to suggest ways in which these problems, which are still
pertinent today, may be resolved.
In
the first chapter of Classical
Music and Postmodern Knowledge,
Kramer accuses analysis as having, in its “zealous will to truth”
promoted
the “rhetoric of impersonality into an epistemological first
principle”, and states that within musicology, the concept of
knowledge needs to be re-situated within the historicity of human
subjects and their discourses (Kramer 1992: 2). Kramer 'undoes'
analysis's rational foundation by asserting that by adopting a
scientific manner and presenting its results as objective, analysis
disguises its roots in the subjectivity of the analyst and makes
implicit the value judgments on which it constructs its claims to
knowledge. “For what if”, Kramer asks, “interpretations
are...contestable, historically
conditioned forms of
knowledge?” (my italics). This position is supported by many later
musicologists, who have gone even further in trying to show that the
'purist' techniques of analysis have a strong root in the ideology
surrounding the Western concert tradition and the culturally
constructed notion of instrumental music as transcendental (Levy
1987, Tomlinson 2003).
Kramer
proceeds to argue for a musicology that makes the historical –
with all its contingencies, subjectivities and cultural constructs –
an object on which to focus rather than deny. He outlines scope for
engagement with feminist theory, popular culture, psychoanalysis,
deconstruction, the histories of sexualities and other forms of
postmodern knowledge. The essential principle of Kramer's
musicology is that it should be a 'dialogue of listening' between
critic and the composer, who provokes questions by making their music
behave in a certain way, and trusts the listener to hear the music
within a field of rhetorical, expressive, and discursive behaviours.
He states this is especially appropriate to 'representative' music;
representation is one of the sites where culture enters music, and
music enters culture. In his third chapter, Kramer presents a
detailed analysis of Haydn's The Creation, using both Schenker
and Tovey to help elucidate the manner in which Die Vorstellung
des Chaos conveys its representation of the origins of the
universe, accounting for the appropriate musical parameters. For
example, Kramer takes the use of melody to be appropriately
fragmentary (as one might expect in a partly-formed universe) and
also locates a 'chaos motive': three notes ascending a minor third in
a double dotted rhythm (e.g mm.22-24). He explains how Haydn treats
the motive to explicate chaos's urgent desire to be lifted into the
cosmos, but also to thwart their aspirations, as they greet the
cadences in bars 39 and 49.
Kramer’s
notion of 'subjectivity' here and in the rest of the book becomes
obfuscated and problematic in its application. For all his apparent
understanding of the problems of the enlightened postmodern academic,
he appears to limit discussion of the (co-dependent and co-extensive)
relationship between subject and object only to disciplinary
classifications of knowledge – equating 'subjectivity' with the
cultural and historical, in marked opposition to the 'objective'
which he relates to quantitative and quasi-mathematical data.
Although initially he undercuts the traditionally conceived notion of
objective by pointing out its origins in subjectivity, he takes up
the same authorial stance and manner of looking at the object that
has traditionally been used by analysis. That is, although he
considers 'extra musical' factors, he does so through from the
perspective of someone who claims they have access to the music as it
'really is'.
Since
not all of Kramer's arguments are fully justified by his musical
examples (Pasler 1997), one could argue that a more nuanced
application of postmodern knowledge would have been slightly more
cautious in conducting a 'dialogue' with the music. For, without any
semantic capacity of its own, music is inarticulate in refuting the
meanings the theorist gives it.2
In Kramer's studies, the distinction between finding meanings and
creating them is markedly obscure. This is demonstrated especially
when he argues that the musical portrayal of 'chaos' extends towards
a notion of 'limitlessness' he turns to quoting the literary
theorist Slavoj
Žižek,
rather than providing a musical example as justification for his
ideas.
Behind
this example lies a deeper epistemological issue: when discussing
music, is there ever a distinct difference between meanings which are
found
and meanings which are made,
or
is there only a gradient? I will return to the role of social context
later in this essay; to delve further into the complications
postmodern theory illuminates between analysis, the academic, and the
'music itself', I
will now turn to Rose Rosengard Subotnik's Deconstructive
Variations.
The
poststructuralist concept of deconstruction, engendered by Jaques
Derrida, has no universally agreed upon definition or form of
application. In fact, deconstruction is resistant to any notion that
would 'fix' its interpretation, precisely because its 'central
principle' (for lack of a more appropriate term) is what Derrida
called Différance –
the notion that there
is always some difference, some delay, between the meaning intended
in an utterance made by a subject, and the meaning received in its
interpretation by another (Glendinning 2011: 54). The issue is more
complex, vast and discursive than this small outline makes clear, but
for the purposes of this essay, this does not matter: Subotnik makes
no claim to provide a full account of any deconstructionist’s work;
rather, the book is an account of the results of the application of
certain 'deconstructive' ideas to a musical text.3
The
chapter that most concerns us, entitled “How Could Chopin's A-Major
Prelude be Deconstructed” presents two, in-depth readings of
Chopin's Prelude op. 28, no. 7, which are incompatible: as Subotnik
observes, “characteristically, a deconstruction results in (at
least) two coherent readings of a single text that coexist but cannot
be reconciled with each other”
(Subotnik 1996:
66). The first, more 'congenial' reading – the one that Subotnik
states the prelude “assigns priority to,” and therefore presents
as the foreground layer of meaning – construes the prelude as a
unified whole. It is divided into 'primary' material, which is
tonally located in the key of A major, and 'supplementary' material,
the climactic chord on the first beat of measure 12 (chord V of B
major). The supplementary
material is defined as such since the piece would still work as a
composition if phrase 6, which contains the chord, behaved like
phrase 2; although Subotnik is keen to remind us the chord is
complementary, not inessential.
Subotnik
claims the workings of the prelude “suggest themselves very
powerfully... as a metaphor for free choice.” By
rupturing the A major tonality,
chord V of B (analogous to a subjective individual) effectively
symbolizes the power of the freely acting subject to have an impact
on its environment. Yet, through its identity as tonally different,
it clarifies its own secondary status, and thus confirms the
governing constructive role of the tonic, A, just as the freely
acting subject depends on some united, governing, rational framework
in order to render its actions intelligible.
In
the second 'deconstructive' reading, Subotnik rips apart the unity
she previously constructed. By replacing the tonal lens she uses to
view the prelude with one that focuses on parameters our academic
tradition may have conditioned us to marginalize, we can construe
phrase 6 and the climactic chord it contains not as a consequential
partner of phrase 5, but as itself, an antecedent.
Thus, we may hear chord V of B-minor as a dramatic and rhetorical
projection of strength, which is disjunct from the rest of the piece
also in terms of its extended range, increased dynamic, and the fact
that the chord is often performed slower tempo, and rolled (for
pianists whose hands do not span a compound major third). In breaking
the symmetry of the 'sensuous' antecedents and 'logical' consequents,
the framework of order in the first reading is dissolved, and the
prelude's is rendered contingent; a structure which, like human life,
may or may not possess meaning.
There
are a number of issues that arise from this interpretation. The first
is similar to the problem encountered within Kramer's analysis: in
her analysis she reaches outwards to explain the prelude in light of
metaphoric associations it has no power to contest. In
extension, Subotnik's interpretation (of both the two readings, and
the relationship between phrase 6 and the rest of the musical
material) as oppositional appears forced. A unified prelude and an
un-unified prelude might be unreconcilable, but do they constitute a
binary opposition? As Brian Hyer observes of deconstructive readings
more generally, “deconstructionists sometimes force mere
differences into oppositions in order to preside, triumphantly over
their undoing” (Hyer 1998: 414).
The
main issue, however, is illuminated by questioning whether Subotnik's
readings actually are deconstructive. As I have stated, what
deconstruction exactly is
falls outside the boundaries of this essay, and Subotnik herself
never claims to have presented an (again, for lack of a better term)
authentic deconstructive model. Yet what Subotnik's analysis reveals
is a weakening of faith in the tools of analysis: an unclear stance
on which parameters should be used to dissect the prelude into its
'essential elements' (necessary in order to explain its inner
workings). In both readings phrases are taken as stable constituent
objects, with phrase 6 as the climax; however, phrase 6's
classification as antecedent or consequent is dependent on whether we
view the prelude in a predominantly tonal sense (as in reading 1) or
whether we include the (traditionally secondary) parameters of range
and dynamic. A third view, articulated by Brian Hyer in light of what
he considers the prelude's 'terseness', is that there are not eight
phrases but two (antecedent) phrases (with cadences). And Kevin
Korsyn contends, in his survey of analyses of Prelude no. 7, and the
rest of Opus 28, there are, in fact, four different ways of reading
the preludes: as unified monads, with separate systems of internal
workings, as nomads, as a cryptocycle, or as an ironic cycle,
depending on which way each prelude's internal workings are defined
in relation with the others' (Korsyn 2003: 101).
Implicitly
demonstrated by the multiplicity of readings – whether contained
within the work of a single “author” or not – is this: the
results of analysis are dependent on the questions analysis asks, and
the parameters through which it chooses to view the work. As
Adam Krims has observed, those working within the field of New
Musicology, despite their critical sophistication, often take for
granted the essentialist premise that music analysis may reveal
something objectively present in the 'music itself' (Krims 1998:
304). In this sense, Subotnik and Kramer's analyses are more
structuralist than poststructuralist, but then so is all analytical
theory: analysis itself seems to encourage us to essentialize
analytical 'tools', whilst poststructuralist thought contests
metalanguage and its essentialist tendencies, and tends to militate
against methodological closure. Indeed, if
there ever was
a binary opposition that needed to be undone, it would have been
between the 'objects' of analysis and their expression in language.
Are
analysis and postmodern knowledge radically incompatible, then? Kofi
Agawu argues: yes. Analysis needs neither cultural context or
postmodern knowledge; theory works best when questions about its
objects are consigned to the periphery, and when matters of social
context form a separate discussion: “The musical text...together
with an explicit methodology, form the basis of theorizing.”
In this sense, analysis needs no justification and should carry
on as it has done before (Agawu 1993: 89-98).
This
barefaced rebutal resulted in a discursive stalemate with Joseph
Kerman, whereby both theorists fought from positions constructed on
different axioms, “misrecognizing the two disciplines dependency on
each other, as they misrecognise the sources of their own identity”.
Agawu undermines his argument by presenting a historical case for it,
and Kerman tries to construct a unified identity for all historical
critics by attempting to detach historical criticism from theory
entirely, obscuring the identities of theorists he admires by
reclassifying them as resembling something like a critic (Korsyn
2003: 88). Korsyn sets forth a list of reforms the academy should
undertake to end the stand-off and let the two disciplines continue
in parallel, with separate methodologies and separate concerns. By
this, all of music's aspects would be represented through undertaking
relative positions in a larger discourse with no singular or
permanent centre.
However,
what I propose as a better solution to Korsyn's notion of parallel
paradigms is implicit within the writings of Kramer and Subotnik, but
never brought to explicit attention: “[For] what if”, Kramer
asks, “we see the music, not as the site where its contexts vanish,
but precisely as the site where they appear?” In Kramer's “dialogue
of listening” he does not undergo the process of listening to
specific performances and documenting the results, but conducts a
hermeneutic analysis of music as a text, and discusses it in relation
to reminisces of performances he has attended previously, or vague,
unspecified, imaginary performances. Likewise, although Subotnik
points to issues within performance (the difficultly of the rolled
chord for her small hands,
the fact that performers often slow down as they approach it with
dread),
specific
performances are not delineated.
However,
refocusing on real performance events allows us to relate music to
social and cultural forces in a more concrete manner. To take an
obvious example, depending on their cultural conditioning, a
performer may choose to roll the climactic chord in phrase 6 of
Chopin's A-Major prelude or not; they may find the passage tricky and
attempt it rather slowly; they may, even chose to play the phrase as
a disjunct from the others which surround it, since personally, they
understand the prelude to be a metaphor for the contingent nature of
all human life and understanding.
Therefore,
we should try and understand music by relating the specifics of a
performance to the larger cultural contexts in which they are
imbedded, for instance: styles, genres, performing trends and
performance occasions. Undoubtedly this creates a more realistic
vision of music's relation to the social and cultural than Kramer's;
however, those who have written on it often fall into a similar
interpretive trap. Writers such as Small (1998) and Attali (1985)
take these microsocialities as the sole locus for theorising the
social in music, idealizing them through a metaphysics of presence
(Born, forthcoming). Accounts like this run the risk of
determining the musical event as
a product of social or ideological forces, when these “social
forces” are what should be explained.
In
advocating a performance approach, I am not stating that performance
is any more resistant to the sort of interpretations music
receives when conceived of as a text. However, performance does limit
these types of interpretation through offering a solid and
accessible contextual framework that we can study, empirically,
through ethnography.
Nicholas Cook and Georgina Born's “Relational musicology” is a
theoretical paradigm that advocates such an approach. Recent work
within the field holds that meaning emerges in encounters between
people, and is not wholly determined by the musical score,
social structures or ideologies. Instead, these are seen to forge the
conditions for the encounters in which culture is negotiated and
reshaped by agents. Through a strong
ethnographic approach which engages with individuals to study these
negotiations in rehearsal and performance, and an assessment of
findings it in relation to larger social theories, we find an
empirically sound way of relating musical practices to their social
and cultural context.
Born
(2007) argues that it is productive to analyse music's myriad
socialities in terms of four planes of social mediation: 1)
Micro-socialities 2) Imagined communities 3) How it refracts wider
social identity formations, and 4) Forces of production. This
framework goes some way to eliminate reductive accounts of music's
relation to the social by holding interactions between these planes
(and the extra-musical factors that they incorporate) are irreducibly
complex, and all four planes have the ability to animate music's
aesthetic, ethical and political dimensions. The anti-reductionist
gains of analysing both the autonomy of distinctive planes of music's
social mediation and, thereby, cross-scalar relations between them
include the potential for contradiction and disjunction. For
performance does not only traverse wider social relations, but it has
the ability to catalyse or act on them, to invert or contest
hierarchical social orders. Genre, for example, is commonly explained
as embodying an assured linkage to the politics of the communities
that construct it (e.g. Negus 1999). However, this does not explain
its power to affect either the reproduction of identity formations,
or a redirection or novel coalition of such formations. Genre should
therefore be analysed as an evolving constellation constituted by the
mutual mediation between two self-organizing entities (music and
identity formations), (Born, forthcoming).
Relational
musicology advocates reshaping the boundaries of the epistemic field,
revealing the concealed ideologies of individual branches, and
extending other branches to form hybridized and multivalent
approaches (Born 2007). In this sense, there is room here for
analysis to be brought back into the picture, as well as occupying an
isolated position within the field as Agawu and Korsyn suggest.
The
manner in which analysis has previously aggregated with different
methodologies has been problematic. Analytical methods have been used
in ethnographies as a manner of recording performances. However, too
often these transcriptions attempt to totalise the experience of the
individual musicians making up the ensemble and abstracts it from the
social processes in which it is embedded, creating a new reified text
which translates rather than explains the experience (Cook 1999:
261). 'Structurally informed
performance' (as urged by Berry or Namour) has also been problematic.
It is prescriptive rather than descriptive in nature, and although it
presents viable options it cannot justify why these are necessarily
better than other
options discovered through performing.
Cook
defines the score not as a textual object with all its meanings
located within it, but instead as a script for social interaction,
which gives us only a certain amount of information to obey in
performance, and leaves the rest as ambiguous, delegating decisions
to performers who will negotiate to fix them for performance
(forthcoming).
Through this 'relational' paradigm, we can work towards
creating different forms of analysis, which does not 'blindly'
dictate performance methods, but poses questions to performance, and
engages with responses. This approach also offers the capacity to
shift analysis away from the purely tonal, and consider other
important musical parameters, including those not present when we
consider music as a text such as gesture and movement.
In conclusion, postmodern knowledge might not have taken musicology
in the direction it originally intended, but opening musicology to
literary theory and deconstructive approaches planted the seeds for
the development of the study of music in relation to the social and
cultural, and the expansion of analytical methodologies.
In particular, I advocate Nick Cook and Georgina Born's approach of
Relational Musicology, in light of its nuanced and realistic
understanding of the complex relationship between music and the
social factors it aggregated with, and its ethnographic focus on
'real' (rather than abstracted) forms of social and cultural
knowledge. Hopefully, this will enable us to make a swifter shift
away from the large body of introspective discourse characteristic of
musicology's last twenty years and engage in a new yet enlightened
focus on our “object” of study.
3434
Words.
Bibliography:
Agawu, Kofi,
“Does Music Theory Need Musicology?” in Current Musicology 53,
special issue, Approaches to the Discipline, ed. Edmund J
Goehring (1993) pp. 89 – 98
Attali,
Noise: The Political Economy of Music, (Minnesota: 1985)
Born,
Georgina, “For a relational Musicology: Music and
Interdisciplinarity, Beyond the Practice Turn”, Journal of the
Royal Musical Association, (2007)
Vol. 135, no. 2, 205–243
Georgina
Born, 'Music and the Social', in M.
Clayton et al (eds), The Cultural Study of Music, 2nd
edition,
(forthcoming:
2012).
Cook,
Nicholas, Analysing Musical Multimedia (Oxford: 1998)
Cook,
Nicholas,' Analysing Performance and Performing Analysis' Rethinking
Music, Cook and Evereist eds.,
(Oxford: 1999)
Cook, Nicholas, Scripting social interaction:
Improvisation, performance, and Western 'art' music'. In
Improvisation and Social Aesthetics, ed. Georgina Born, Eric
Lewis, and Will Straw. Hanover, NH: Wesleyan University Press
(forthcoming)
Cook,
Nicholas, 'Theorising Musical Meaning', Music Theory Spectrum,
Vol. 23, No. 2 (Fall 2001), pp. 170-195
Everett Maus,
Fred, 'The Disciplined Subject of Musical Analysis' in Andrew
Dell'Antonio, ed., Beyond Structural Listening: Postmodern Modes
of Hearing (Berkely and Los Angeles: 2004)
Glendinning,
Simon, Derrida: A Very Short Introduction, (Oxford University
Press: 2011)
Hyer, Brian,
“Review: Deconstructive Variations: Music and Reason in Western
Society by Rose Rosengard Subotnik; Classical Music and Postmodern
Knowledge by Lawrence Kramer,” Journal of the American
Musicological Society, Vol. 51, No. 2 (Summer, 1998), pp. 409 –
424
Kerman,
Joseph, Musicology, (London: 1985)
Kerman,
Joseph, “How We Dot into Analysis and How to Get Out,” Critical
Enquiry 7, (1980), reprinted in Write all These Down: Essays
on Music, (Berkely: University of California Press, 1999), 12–32
Korsyn,
Kevin, Decentering Music: A Critique of Contemporary Musical
Research, (Oxford: 2003)
Kramer,
Lawrence, Classical Music and Postmodern Knowledge, (University
of California Press: 1992)
Krims, Adam,
“Disciplining Deconstruction (For Music Analysis)” 19th
Century Music, Vol. 21. No. 3 (Spring 1998), pp. 297 – 324
Kramer,
Lawrence, Music as Cultural Practice, 1800–1900 (Berkeley and Los
Angeles, 1990)
Levy, Janet
M, 'Covert and Casual Values in Recent Writings About Music', The
Journal of Musicology, Vol. 5, No. 1 (1987)
Littlefield,
Richard, “The Silence of the Frames”, Music
Theory Online 2,
(1996)
Negus, Keith,
Music Genres and Corporate Cultures (Routledge: 1999)
Pasler, Jann,
“Review: Classical Music and Postmodern Knowledge”, Notes,
Second Series, Vol. 53, No. 3 (Mar., 1997), pp. 756 – 761
Scherzinger,
Martin, “The finale of Mahler's Seventh Symphony: A Deconstructive
Reading” Music
Analysis
14 (1996), pp. 1–25
Snarrenberg,
Robert, “The Play of Différance:
Brahms's Intermezzo, Op. 118, No. 2,” In Theory
Only 10 (October 1987), pp.
1–25
Small,
Christopher, Musicking: The Meanings of Performing and Listening
(Wesleyan: 1998)
Subotnik,
Rose Rosengard , Deconstructive Variations: Music and Reason in
Western Society, (University of Minnesota Press: 1996)
Tomlinson,
Gary, “Music, Anthropology, History”, in Middleton, ed., The
Cultural Study of Music (Routledge: 2003)
1Analysis
is reflective of modernist values more largely, in that it prizes
the rational, the constantive, the quantitive,
the
scientific and the masculine.
2Nicholas
Cook explores the complex interactions between music and text in
'Theorising Musical Meaning', Music
Theory Spectrum, Vol.
23, No. 2 (Fall 2001), pp. 170-195
3The
other attempts at applying deconstruction (which encounter the same
problems) are: Snarrenberg (1987)
Scherzinger (1996) Kramer (1990) Littlefield (1996).
No comments:
Post a Comment